Skip to main content

Quote for the Day

"I’ll conclude with a brief comment on the exceedingly low standard Bill [Craig] sets for a “good” philosophical argument. The premises don’t even need to be “plausible,” he says – “just more plausible than their opposites.” But surely, when you don’t know enough even to say, “This is plausible,” you don’t have a foundation on which to build an argument for a conclusion that you can believe! To see just how bad the problem is, suppose that each of the logically independent premises Bill needs to get all the way to the conclusion that a personal God created the universe meets this low standard. By way of illustration, suppose that there are just four logically independent premises, and make the very generous assumption that the probability is two to one in favor of each of them. Then the probability that all of them are true is less than 0.2, and the probability that at least one of them is false is greater than 0.8! Imagine a ladder with four rungs, and suppose that the probability that at least one of them will break is in the neighborhood of 0.8. Would you trust that ladder? No? Then you shouldn’t put too awfully much weight on this version of the cosmological argument!"

-Wes Morriston (from his opening statement in is dialogue with William Lane Craig)


Wes's comments on the dialogue with Craig can be found here.

Comments

Jake said…
I've also thought that Craig's standard for the acceptance of premises to be problematic because it looks like it runs straight into a Sorites sequence. Consider a pile of 1001 grains of sand, then construct an argument with 1000 premises of the form, "If X grains of sand is a pile, then X-1 grains of sand is a pile," yielding the conclusion that 1 grain of sand is a pile. Each premise is more plausible than not, but the conclusion is obviously absurd. If we applied Craig's criterion, then it looks like we should just accept the conclusion of the argument, in spite of it's obvious absurdity. I think you've previously defended the notion of taking disjunctive positions when disputing the premises of an argument, and I think such an approach is quite right and harmonizes with Morriston's point well and avoids this sort of Soritical concern.
cadfan17 said…
Ironically, the youtube community was hammering Craig on this about a year ago. They're surprisingly good about this sort of thing, if you know where to look.

Craig responded with a lengthy website post that probably dropped his Evangelical college student reader's grades in philosophy by at least two letters.

He argued that one cannot assign numbers to these sorts of statements of probability. Instead, you can just use vague statements like "more plausible than their opposite." But of course anyone with the most basic of mathematical literacy can recognize that as a red herring argument. The mathematical relationship between the probabilities of your premises and the probability of your conclusions holds true even if you refuse to assign numerical values.

He also argued that anyone who contradicted him on these points was denying the validity of all deductive reasoning. He essentially used a radical skepticism based argument to claim that if nothing is truly certain, then you must accept that deduction takes place with uncertain premises, or else you must reject all deductive reasoning. Again, it was a red herring, obviously.

And in the midst of all that he continued to maintain that if you have an argument where each premise is more plausible than its negation, and where the argument follows the forms of deductive reasoning, then it is "irrational" not to believe the conclusions of the argument.

Reading this post was the point where I started actively disrespecting him. Before I didn't have any particular like or dislike for him, but after that post, dozens of religious kids swarmed the youtube channels that started the debate, all convinced that deductive logic worked the way Craig said it did.

Craig took the opportunity to use his soapbox to actively and intentionally make people dumber.
Monte said…
Craig's reply would be along these lines: http://www.reasonablefaith.org/site/News2?page=NewsArticle&id=8273
exapologist said…
Thanks for the pointer, you two. I'll give it a look.

Popular posts from this blog

Epicurean Cosmological Arguments for Matter's Necessity

One can find, through the writings of Lucretius, a powerful yet simple Epicurean argument for matter's (factual or metaphysical) necessity. In simplest terms, the argument is that since matter exists, and since nothing can come from nothing, matter is eternal and uncreated, and is therefore at least a factually necessary being. 
A stronger version of Epicurus' core argument can be developed by adding an appeal to something in the neighborhood of origin essentialism. The basic line of reasoning here is that being uncreated is an essential property of matter, and thus that the matter at the actual world is essentially uncreated.
Yet stronger versions of the argument could go on from there by appealing to the principle of sufficient reason to argue that whatever plays the role of being eternal and essentially uncreated does not vary from world to world, and thus that matter is a metaphysically necessary being.
It seems to me that this broadly Epicurean line of reasoning is a co…

CfP: Inquiry: New Work on the Existence of God

NEW WORK ON THE EXISTENCE OF GOD
In recent years, methods and concepts in logic, metaphysics and epistemology have become more and more sophisticated. For example, much new, subtle and interesting work has been done on modality, grounding, explanation and infinity, in both logic, metaphysics as well as epistemology. The three classical arguments for the existence of God – ontological arguments, cosmological arguments and fine-tuning arguments – all turn on issues of modality, grounding, explanation and infinity. In light of recent work, these arguments can - and to some extent have - become more sophisticated as well. Inquiry hereby calls for new and original papers in the intersection of recent work in logic, metaphysics and epistemology and the three main types of arguments for the existence of God. 


The deadline is 31 January 2017. Direct queries to einar.d.bohn at uia.no.

Andrew Moon's New Paper on Recent Work in Reformed Epistemology...

...in the latest issue of Philosophy Compass. Here's the abstract:
Reformed epistemology, roughly, is the thesis that religious belief can be rational without argument. After providing some background, I present Plantinga's defense of reformed epistemology and its influence on religious debunking arguments. I then discuss three objections to Plantinga's arguments that arise from the following topics: skeptical theism, cognitive science of religion, and basicality. I then show how reformed epistemology has recently been undergirded by a number of epistemological theories, including phenomenal conservatism and virtue epistemology. I end by noting that a good objection to reformed epistemology must criticize either a substantive epistemological theory or the application of that theory to religious belief; I also show that the famous Great Pumpkin Objection is an example of the former. And if a copy should make its way to my inbox...

UPDATE: Thanks!