...on New Books Network. Thanks to Yujin Nagasawa for the pointer.
Quick Links
- Book
- 200 (or so) Arguments for Atheism
- Index: Assessing Theism
- Why Mainstream Scholars Think Jesus Was A Failed Apocalyptic Prophet
- What's Wrong With Plantinga's Proper Functionalism?
- Draper's Critique of Behe's Design Argument
- The Failure of Plantinga's Free Will Defense
- 100 Arguments for God Answered
- Thomistic Arguments for God Answered
- On a Common Apologetic Strategy
- On Caring About and Pursuing Truth
- A Priori Naturalism, A Priori Inerrantism, and the Bible
Theism's Explanatory Gap Problem
Ever since at least Russell (1927), many philosophers[1] have argued that materialism – and, I now point out, classical theism – have an “explanatory gap” problem of another sort. For science only tells us about the structure and dynamics of matter -- i.e., its extrinsic, relational properties -- and not its intrinsic properties[2]. As D.M. Armstrong (1968) put it:
"...[I]f we look at properties of physical objects that physicists are prepared to allow them, such as mass, electric charge, or momentum, these show a distressing tendency to dissolve into relations one object has to another. What, then, are the things that have these relations to each other? Must they not have a non-relational nature if they are to sustain relations? But what is this nature? Physics does not tell us." (p. 282)
Subsequent progress in science only seems to underscore this point (cf. Ladyman and Ross 2007; Davidson 2014). Many thus now argue for ontic structural realism, according to which reality consists of relations without relata, and it is only “relations all the way down”. Unfortunately, to date, even the most strident defenders of ontic structuralism have failed to give a coherent account of the view, and many of its sympathizers admit that the current evidence fails to support its most plausible construals (cf. McKenzie 2017). Incoherence threatens. This is the explanatory gap problem for both conservative naturalism and theism: both views give us a physical universe with a hollow core, as neither provides the resources to provide intrinsic properties to ground its extrinsic, relational properties.
There is thus pressure to say that there must be some stock of intrinsic properties to physical reality, and yet physical reality seems to lack such properties. What is a naturalist or a theist to do? The Russellian monist answers: The only intrinsic properties we know of are phenomenal properties of subjective experience. The Russellian monist thus posits that phenomenal properties ground the relational properties of physics. Happily, then, Russellian monism appears to solve both the hard problem of consciousness and the intrinsic properties problem in one stroke. The structure-and dynamics-argument therefore offers another powerful line of support for liberal naturalism vis-a-vis theism.
----------------------------------------------------------
[1] See, for example, Russell (1927), Strawson (1986), Chalmers (1996), Stoljar (2006), Pereboom (2011), Alter & Nagasawa (2012), Alter (2016) and Goff (2017).
[2]Lewis (1986) argued that shape is an intrinsic property of material objects, but Davidson (2014) has argued persuasively that shape is relative to a given inertial reference frame.
References:
Alter, Torin. 2016. “The Structure and Dynamics Argument Against Materialism”, Nous 50 (4): 794-815.
-----. and Yujin Nagasawa. 2015. Consciousness in the physical world: Perspectives on Russellian Monism (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Armstrong, D.M. 1968. A Materialist Theory of Mind. New York: Routledge.
Chalmers, David. 1996. The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Davidson, Matthew. 2014. “Special Relativity and the Intrinsicality of Shape”, Analysis 74 (1): 57-58.
Goff, Phillip. 2017. Consciousness and Fundamental Reality, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ladyman, James and Don Ross, with David Spurrett and John Collier. 2007. Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized, Oxford University Press.
Lewis, David. 1986. On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
McKenzie, Kerry. 2017. “Ontic Structural Realism”, Philosophy Compass 12 (4): e12399.
Pereboom, Derk. 2011. Consciousness and the Prospects for Physicalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Russell, Bertrand. 1927. The Analysis of Matter. London: George Allen & Unwin.
Stoljar, Daniel. 2006. Ignorance and Imagination: The Epistemic Origin of the Problem of Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Strawson, Galen. 2008. Real Materialism: And Other Essays (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Cambridge Elements in Philosophy of Religion: Free Downloads!
For readers of this blog who don't know already, the books in the Cambridge Elements in Philosophy of Religion are available for free download for two weeks after their original publication!
Check them out!
Check them out!
Theism, Substance Dualism, Personal Identity, Evil, and Quantum Mechanics
(Extremely rough draft.)
Ever since at least Ladyman and Ross's Every Thing Must Go (with David Wallace, Peter Lewis, David Albert, Tim Maudlin and many others in chorus) more and more philosophers have been coming to grips with the need for radical revisions in traditional analytic metaphysics in the light of quantum mechanics (QM) (cf. Jenann Ismael, Alyssa Ney, Peter Lewis, Kerry McKenzie, Jessica Wilson, Jonathan Schaffer, Ted Sider, Shamik Dasgupta, and many others).[1] However (aside from worries for the causal principle in cosmological arguments), it seems that the waves of the quantum revolution have yet to be felt in contemporary analytic philosophy of religion. I noted one potential implication on another occasion. Here are a few more.
Ever since at least Ladyman and Ross's Every Thing Must Go (with David Wallace, Peter Lewis, David Albert, Tim Maudlin and many others in chorus) more and more philosophers have been coming to grips with the need for radical revisions in traditional analytic metaphysics in the light of quantum mechanics (QM) (cf. Jenann Ismael, Alyssa Ney, Peter Lewis, Kerry McKenzie, Jessica Wilson, Jonathan Schaffer, Ted Sider, Shamik Dasgupta, and many others).[1] However (aside from worries for the causal principle in cosmological arguments), it seems that the waves of the quantum revolution have yet to be felt in contemporary analytic philosophy of religion. I noted one potential implication on another occasion. Here are a few more.
Prima facie, on any plausible interpretation of quantum mechanics (Bohmian, Everettian, and GRW), there are many worlds/universes. As Peter Lewis points out, non-Everrettian interpretations of quantum mechanics are just many-worlds accounts in denial[2]. This has serious implications for the metaphysics of personal identity and other issues related to philosophy of religion.
For example, take standard theistic accounts of substance dualism, and take the increasingly popular Everettian interpretation of QM (in fact, strictly speaking, it's not an interpretation: it just is QM). On that account, humans are constantly branching, hydra-like, into hugely many alternate universes, at virtually every moment of their lives. But if so, then prima facie, either (i) only one branch is you, or (ii) they all are you. On (i), God creates (directly, ex nihilo, or indirectly, through natural processes) new souls for each branch self at virtually every moment. On (ii), you have many selves. On either option, the sameness of soul account of personal identity is starting to look seriously unmotivated.
Furthermore, what are we to make of the afterlife? On (ii), all of your counterpart branch souls have an existence in an afterlife. Now combine that with the traditional doctrine of the soul being joined to a physical body at the final judgement. Prima facie, our world essentially involves QM and branching universes, in which case ,prima facie, so does any post-resurrection universe. Prima facie, all of the branching selves will be resurrected in different alternate universes, with counterpart Christs. On (i), it's hard to get an intelligible grasp of how all of my branching selves could be "me", each in their own resurrected bodies in alternate universes.
Furthermore, what are we to make of the afterlife? On (ii), all of your counterpart branch souls have an existence in an afterlife. Now combine that with the traditional doctrine of the soul being joined to a physical body at the final judgement. Prima facie, our world essentially involves QM and branching universes, in which case ,prima facie, so does any post-resurrection universe. Prima facie, all of the branching selves will be resurrected in different alternate universes, with counterpart Christs. On (i), it's hard to get an intelligible grasp of how all of my branching selves could be "me", each in their own resurrected bodies in alternate universes.
Furthermore, what are we to make of the person and work of Christ? For example, Jesus has many branch selves. Which one is the "real" Jesus? One? Some? All? Presumably, then, there are many Christs, and there will have to be many crucifixions. From this example, it becomes apparent that a host of other problems arise for the incarnation, atonement, trinity, and related doctrines.
Finally, there are infinitely many decohering branches of the universal wave function, such that infinitely many branches contain gratuitous evil.
In short, it looks as though quantum mechanics poses serious problems for both substance dualism and for theism. In fact, it's looking as though QM, all by itself, is incompatible with-- or, at the very least, highly surprising on -- traditional accounts of Christian theism and religious monotheism in general. Prima facie, then, QM provides at least strong abductive evidence against traditional monotheism.
-----
[1] The other main revolution in physics is relativistic quantum field theory (RQFT), according to which fields are more fundamental than particles: what we call 'particles' are really just field excitations. But that is another can of worms.
[1] The other main revolution in physics is relativistic quantum field theory (RQFT), according to which fields are more fundamental than particles: what we call 'particles' are really just field excitations. But that is another can of worms.
[2] Lewis, Peter J. Quantum Ontology: A Guide to the Metaphysics of Quantum Mechanics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016).
200 (or so) Arguments for Atheism
A popular view in contemporary analytic philosophy of religion is that while there are many arguments[1] for theism -- cosmological, ontological, and teleological arguments; moral arguments; arguments from consciousness; etc. (by Plantinga's lights, two dozen or so), there are only two arguments for atheism[2], viz., the problem of evil and (more recently) the problem of divine hiddenness. Indeed, some argue that the problem of divine hiddenness reduces to a version of the problem of evil, and thus that there is only one argument -- or at most, one category of argument -- for atheism.
This is a misconception. Here are over 200 arguments for atheism, spanning 28 categories:
I. Cosmological-Type Arguments
1. Epicurean cosmological arguments for naturalism
2. The argument from metaphysical infinitism/coherentism
2. The argument from metaphysical infinitism/coherentism
6. A Leibnizian-style cosmological argument against theism
7. Smith's Kalam cosmological argument for atheism
7. Smith's Kalam cosmological argument for atheism
9. A grounding-based cosmological argument from one-category ontology
10. The Spinozistic argument from negative PSR to naturalism
10. The Spinozistic argument from negative PSR to naturalism
II. Ontological-Type Arguments
17. Goff's conceivability argument for atheism
18. A minimal modal ontological argument for naturalism
19. Quantum modal realist ontological argument for naturalism
18. A minimal modal ontological argument for naturalism
19. Quantum modal realist ontological argument for naturalism
20. The ontological argument for Spinozism
21. Maitzen’s ontological argument for atheism
22. Inductive arguments against Anselmianism
23. Another ontological disproof of theism
21. Maitzen’s ontological argument for atheism
22. Inductive arguments against Anselmianism
23. Another ontological disproof of theism
26. Another argument from fine-tuning against theism (see also)
27. Atheistic teleological arguments (see also)
27. Atheistic teleological arguments (see also)
42. The problem of natural nonbelief
43. The argument from anti-religious experience and properly basic atheistic belief
43. The argument from anti-religious experience and properly basic atheistic belief
45. The argument from naturalistic explanations of religious practices
46. The argument from the ineffectiveness of prayer (see also)
47. The argument from theistic demographics
48. The common core/diversity dilemma
46. The argument from the ineffectiveness of prayer (see also)
47. The argument from theistic demographics
48. The common core/diversity dilemma
50. Smith's argument from felt meanings of the world
VI. Arguments from Morality and Moral Psychology
51. The argument from the autonomy of normative ethics
52. The argument from the autonomy of metaethics
53. The argument from normative uncertainty
VI. Arguments from Morality and Moral Psychology
51. The argument from the autonomy of normative ethics
52. The argument from the autonomy of metaethics
53. The argument from normative uncertainty
54. The argument from blameless moral ignorance
55. The argument from moral psychology
56. The argument from lack of character
57. The argument from lack of extensive empathy
58. The argument from ordinary morality
59. The argument from moral epistemology
60. The argument from meager moral fruits
55. The argument from moral psychology
56. The argument from lack of character
57. The argument from lack of extensive empathy
58. The argument from ordinary morality
59. The argument from moral epistemology
60. The argument from meager moral fruits
VII. Arguments from the Meaning of Life
63. Sartrean arguments for gravely diminished meaning in a theistic universe
63. Sartrean arguments for gravely diminished meaning in a theistic universe
66. Betenson's argument from futility in a theistic universe
67. The argument from excessive "anti-matter", or anti-meaning, in a theistic universe (see also)
67. The argument from excessive "anti-matter", or anti-meaning, in a theistic universe (see also)
VIII. Arguments from Consciousness and Personhood
73. The argument from substance dualism to non-theism
73. The argument from substance dualism to non-theism
75, 76. The problem(s) of dissociative identity disorder
77. The argument from the mind’s dependence on the brain
78. The argument from quantum mechanics against theistic accounts of personal identity, related issues
77. The argument from the mind’s dependence on the brain
78. The argument from quantum mechanics against theistic accounts of personal identity, related issues
X. Arguments from Reason
XI. Arguments from Logic
XII. Arguments from Abstract Objects
86. The argument from the uncreatability/metaphysical independence of abstracta
87. The argument from abstracta as God’s metaphysical parts
88. The argument from God’s existence as a derivative being that supervenes upon platonic modal space
89. The Benacerraf argument against God’s knowledge of abstracta
90. The argument from one-category ontology
86. The argument from the uncreatability/metaphysical independence of abstracta
87. The argument from abstracta as God’s metaphysical parts
88. The argument from God’s existence as a derivative being that supervenes upon platonic modal space
89. The Benacerraf argument against God’s knowledge of abstracta
90. The argument from one-category ontology
XIII. Arguments from the Nature of Causation
XIV. Nomological Arguments
XV. Arguments from General Ontology, Metaphysics, and Metametaphysics (that Don't Fit Neatly Into other Categories)
98. The argument from strong ontological nihilism
99. The argument from neo-Carnapian metametaphysics
100. The argument from modal normativism
101. The argument from necessitarianism
99. The argument from neo-Carnapian metametaphysics
100. The argument from modal normativism
101. The argument from necessitarianism
XVI. Epistemological Arguments
105. The argument from theism to radical skepticism
105. The argument from theism to radical skepticism
106. The argument from mitigated modal skepticism
107. The argument from epistemic permissivism
108. The argument from pragmatic encroachment
109. The argument from peer religious disagreement
107. The argument from epistemic permissivism
108. The argument from pragmatic encroachment
109. The argument from peer religious disagreement
110, 111. The problem(s) of religious luck
112. The argument from Mandevillian intelligence
113. The argument from secondary qualities against the reliability of perception
114. The argument from Bayesian theories of perception (esp. prediction error minimization theories)
115. The argument from wave function realism against the reliability of perception
116. The problem of theistic evidentialist philosophers
XVII. Arguments from Aesthetics
117. The argument from ugliness
118. The argument from revulsion
XVIII. Normative Arguments (Apart from problems of evil)
119. The argument from the impropriety of worship
120. The argument from autonomy
112. The argument from Mandevillian intelligence
113. The argument from secondary qualities against the reliability of perception
114. The argument from Bayesian theories of perception (esp. prediction error minimization theories)
115. The argument from wave function realism against the reliability of perception
116. The problem of theistic evidentialist philosophers
XVII. Arguments from Aesthetics
117. The argument from ugliness
118. The argument from revulsion
XVIII. Normative Arguments (Apart from problems of evil)
119. The argument from the impropriety of worship
120. The argument from autonomy
122. Cliffordian arguments from the impropriety of belief without sufficient evidence (and the failure of Plantinga's Reformed Epistemology)
XIX. Arguments from Divine Hiddenness and Non-Belief
123. Deductive arguments from divine hiddenness
124. Probabilistic arguments from divine hiddenness
123. Deductive arguments from divine hiddenness
124. Probabilistic arguments from divine hiddenness
126. Drange's argument from non-belief
XX. Arguments from Incoherence Within/Among the Divine Attributes and Related Matters (Incomplete. These just scratch the surface. For more, see e.g. Oppy's Describing Gods)
XX. Arguments from Incoherence Within/Among the Divine Attributes and Related Matters (Incomplete. These just scratch the surface. For more, see e.g. Oppy's Describing Gods)
129. Foreknowledge
132. Divine freedom (See also)
133. Eternity
135. Maximality
136. Perfection
137. Personhood (see also)
138. Creator and Sustainer
139. Divine consciousness
140. A new paradox of omnipotence
141. The aloneness argument
139. Divine consciousness
140. A new paradox of omnipotence
141. The aloneness argument
XXI. Arguments from Lower Comparative Prior Probability
XXII. Arguments from Explanatory Inferiority
XXIII. Arguments from Rival Supernaturalisms and/or Worldviews with Equal or Greater Explanatory Power and Related Matters
162. The problem of classical deism
179. Law's Evil-god challenge (see also)
180. The problem of the inclusive disjunction of rival supernaturalisms/worldviews
XXIV. Arguments from the Success of Naturalistic Explanations
XXV. Arguments from Private Evidence
182. Bartolome's argument from private evidence
XXVI. Arguments from Evil
182. Bartolome's argument from private evidence
XXVI. Arguments from Evil
192. The problem of infant suffering
193. The argument from flourishing/languishing
194. The Darwinian problem of evil
193. The argument from flourishing/languishing
194. The Darwinian problem of evil
198. Monaghan's new logical problem of evil
199. The argument from religious evil
200. The argument from divine evil
201. The argument from hell
202. The argument from the requirement of divine interference (see also)
199. The argument from religious evil
200. The argument from divine evil
201. The argument from hell
202. The argument from the requirement of divine interference (see also)
203. The argument from eternally separated lovers
204. The argument from inhospitable environment
205. The argument from teleological evil
204. The argument from inhospitable environment
205. The argument from teleological evil
206. The argument from evil natural laws
207. The argument from natural inequalities
208. The argument from social evil
209. The argument from insect suffering
210. The argument from tragic moral dilemmas
211. Sterba's new deductive argument from evil
212. The argument from unfairness
213. The problem of the death of most humans before the age of accountability
214. The argument from the harm of coming into existence
215. The argument from physiological horrors
216. The argument from heaven
207. The argument from natural inequalities
208. The argument from social evil
209. The argument from insect suffering
210. The argument from tragic moral dilemmas
211. Sterba's new deductive argument from evil
212. The argument from unfairness
213. The problem of the death of most humans before the age of accountability
214. The argument from the harm of coming into existence
215. The argument from physiological horrors
216. The argument from heaven
224. Morriston's problem of evil divine commands (e.g., genocide)
(See also these collections on problems of evil)
XXVII. Pragmatic/Prudential Arguments
XVIII. Cumulative case/Combinatorial Arguments
235. Oppy’s abductive cumulative case argument for naturalism
235. Oppy’s abductive cumulative case argument for naturalism
236. Leon’s abductive cumulative case argument for liberal naturalism
237. Draper’s Bayesian cumulative case argument against theism
237. Draper’s Bayesian cumulative case argument against theism
239. Various cumulative IBE arguments from large conjunctive disjuncts of 1-231.
Some things worthy of note. First, there are very many more arguments for atheism than commonly supposed. Second, while categorization is inevitably somewhat arbitrary, there are clearly very many more types of atheistic arguments than commonly supposed -- on my reckoning, 27 other types of atheistic argument besides the problem of evil. Third, the list doesn't include arguments specifically against orthodox Christianity. If it did, the list would be considerably longer. Fourth, roughly 75-80% of atheistic arguments have nothing to do with the problem of evil -- problems of evil are in the minority.
Fifth, the evidence against theism appears to be systemic -- it provides non-trivial grounds for thinking the data from virtually every major aspect of reality (e.g.: the origin, existence, and structure of the universe; consciousness; agency; morality and moral psychology; reason; logic; abstract objects; the nature of causation; the laws of nature; epistemology; religions, religious practices, and religious experience; aesthetics; the meaning of life; general ontology, metaphysics, and meta-metaphysics; and yes, suffering and hiddenness, too) points away from theism and towards some form of naturalism. One can cull very large subsets of compatible arguments from the list above to generate a variety of large abductive cumulative case arguments. Prima facie, there is very strong promise that when this is done, naturalism will embody the theoretical virtues (e.g., simplicity, scope, conservatism, etc.) better than orthodox theism. I would argue that this remains so even after throwing in all the viable data points standardly appealed to in the case for theism, in which case the relevant data renders a form of naturalism more probable than orthodox theism. (A similar point applies to taking all these data points to run a comprehensive Bayesian argument for naturalism.)
Sixth, the previous points constitute non-trivial grounds for thinking the case for atheism doesn't essentially depend on the success of the problem of evil and hiddenness, in which case theists have much more work to do besides addressing those arguments.
Finally, most people who care about arguments for and against theism are adherents of some form of orthodox religious monotheism or other. Among such groups, it's typically thought that the case for their faith must be persuasive, such that no (or almost no) mature, rational, properly functioning human being who appraised the relevant evidence could non-culpably fail to believe after assessing it (on the grounds that (i) God holds people morally responsible for their belief, and (ii) God would be less than perfectly good if he held people morally responsible for their belief if the evidence were less than persuasive). Thus, consider some rational, mature, properly functioning adult agnostic, Joe, who has strongly grasped, internalized, and carefully appraised the above arguments, as well as all the arguments for theism on the other side of the ledger. Suppose further that after long and careful reflection, Joe finds the grounds for atheism to be either stronger than those for theism, or at least, counterbalanced with them. Finally, suppose that Joe thereby either disbelieves or suspends judgement about theism. According to the group of theists specified just above, there can be no one like Joe: The evidence for orthodox monotheism is so good that for any person S, if S is a rational, mature, properly functioning agent, and (after careful reflection and deliberation) S fails to find the evidence to support theism over atheism, or if S merely finds the evidence to be counterbalanced -- or indeed, if S finds themself unable to tell, with any confidence, which way the evidence points -- then S is morally culpable for failing to believe in the relevant version of orthodox monotheism. In light of the case for atheism expressed in the arguments listed above, this looks to be implausible, if not ridiculous.
-----------------------------------------
Notes:
[1] Here and henceforth, I use the notion of an argument broadly, so as to include deductive, inductive, and abductive arguments. I also follow Richard Swinburne in recognizing the distinction between what he calls C-inductive arguments (which are arguments that raise the probabilities of their conclusions at least to some degree, although not necessarily rendering their conclusions more probable than not) and P-inductive arguments (which are arguments that raise the probabilities of their conclusions above 1/2), and include both C-inductive and P-inductive arguments to count as arguments for theism and for atheism.
[2] Here and henceforth, I follow Jeanine Diller and Paul Draper in distinguishing between global atheism (the denial of all gods) and local atheism (denial of a specific god or type of god). I'm taking the arguments in the list below to be arguments for local atheism with respect to the god of orthodox monotheism (although many arguments on the list provide at least some grounds for rejecting at least some other types of gods).
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)
A Modal Cosmological Argument for Atheism
Consider the following principle: WEAK PMC: Possibly, every concrete object (and aggregate of such) that has an originating or sustaining e...